CLARENCE THOMAS AND THE LOST CONSTITUTION

by Myron Magnet

 

(This article was originally published in Imprimus, the Hillsdale College Bulletin, Vol. 48,#9, Sept. 2019)

           

Background material for this article.

Point #1. The American founders decided upon one set of laws for everyone.  This was a radical legal doctrine.  Most nations, at that time, had one set of laws for the common people and another set for the leaders or rulers.  This was the situation in Great Britain at the time of the founding of the United States in 1776. 

Even today, the rulers in many nations do pretty much whatever they wish.  This is called license, not freedom or liberty.  Freedom and liberty in the legal sense mean that one must respect the rights of others.  License means one does not have to respect the rights of others.  This is how things work in many nations today.

Furthermore, the American founders decided that their laws would be based on the British laws for the commoners, or common people, not the laws for the royalty and not the laws for the church.  The basis for American law would be the British Common Law.   

This set of laws is firmly based upon the Ten Commandments of Moses and the Golden Rule (do unto others as you would have them do unto you).  In other words, Biblical admonitions are the proper context of the US Constitution and all US law.   However, you would not know it judging by recent Supreme Court decisions on subjects such as abortion, homosexuality, and many others, as well.

This is not mentioned in this article, but it is the critical CONTEXT of the American Declaration of Independence, the National Constitution, and the Constitutions of each state in America. 

 

Point #2. The article below also does not mention the continuing mix-up in America of State Citizenship versus national citizenship.  Only the State Citizenship is real, in fact. 

The Fourteenth Amendment to the US Constitution (1868) set up an inferior status for the freed slaves after the US Civil War.  They were not given the same State Citizenship as everyone else.  This, in itself, is a horror.  However, even worse, this inferior status of a Ònational citizenshipÓ has now been extended to all Americans.  In other words, Americans have been cheated out of their sovereign State Citizenship. 

Americans would be outraged to know about this, but very few understand it.  One would think that the legal profession would be outraged by this, but they go along or they are disbarred.  This means they lose the ability to practice law.  It is exactly like the doctors who should be outraged at the proliferation of toxic vaccines and other problems, but they are silent or they can lose their medical licenses. 

ÒResidentsÓ, not citizens.  If you read the laws carefully, you will see that they refer not to the Citizens (with a capital C), but often to ÒresidentsÓ.  This is a demeaning and purposefully derogatory word used throughout todayÕs United States Code, or the book of national laws.  For example, the income tax is a Òresident income taxÓ.

This is done because the US Congress does not have the authority to pass many laws for Citizens.  However, Americans are not residents.  They are Citizens.

ÒPersonsÓ, not citizens.  Many laws in America are written for ÒpersonsÓ.  This is another derogatory and demeaning word that can include citizens but also includes foreigners who are not citizens.  This is its meaning in the US Constitution in Article I, Sections 2, 3 and 9.  At least there, the word is capitalized.  The word Person means anyone at all, including non-Citizens.

TodayÕs laws are written for persons because the US Congress and the state governments do not have the authority to write most laws for American Citizens.

Even worse, if you look up the definition of a ÒpersonÓ in the Internal Revenue Code, for example, it states that a person includes Òcorporations, partnerships and trusts.Ó  But those who would destroy the nation have the people and the judges and juries believing that the word ÔpersonÕ applies to the Citizens.  It is a trick to make people think the law applies to them, when it does not.  It is a sad commentary on the legal profession, who are supposed to know the law and to teach it to the people.

ÒSubjectsÓ, not citizens.  Furthermore, Americans are now ÒsubjectsÓ of the government rather than sovereign citizens.  If you donÕt believe this, read the 14th Amendment To the US Constitution. 

This is another demeaning and derogatory word to replace the word Citizen.  The use of the word ÒsubjectÓ to describe the people comes from Great Britain, where the king or queen ruled and the people were his or her ÒsubjectsÓ.

ÒNationalsÓ, not Citizens.  A final insult to the people of America found in the laws today is calling them American nationals, rather than sovereign Citizens.

 

Point #3. The article below does not mention the serious mix-up in America in which the Congress of the United States has two very different jobs.  They have limited authority to enact laws for the 50 States AND they have basically unlimited authority to write laws for the territories and possessions of the United States, and for the District of Columbia. 

These two jobs have become thoroughly mixed up together. As a result, the US Congress passes laws for the entire nation that it does not have the authority to enact.

These are just a few of the ways the intent of the US Constitution has been perverted.  It helps explain why America is no longer the land of liberty that it once was.  The following article does not stress these points nearly enough.

 

(editing note: To make this important article more understandable, we have added many paragraph separations and several sub-headings, and changed two words to simpler ones.)

******

 

CLARENCE THOMAS AND THE LOST CONSTITUTION

 

Clarence Thomas is our eraÕs most consequential jurist, as radical as he is brave. During his almost three decades on the bench, he has been laying out a blueprint for remaking Supreme Court jurisprudence.

His template is the Constitution as the Framers wrote it during that hot summer in Philadelphia 232 years ago, when they aimed to design Ògood government from reflection and choice,Ó as Alexander Hamilton put it in the first Federalist, rather than settle for a regime formed, as are most in history, by Òaccident and force.Ó

In ThomasÕs view, what the Framers achieved remains as modern and up-to-date—as avant-garde, even—as it was in 1787.

What the Framers envisioned was a self-governing republic. Citizens would no longer be ruled.

Under laws made by their elected representatives, they would be free to work out their own happiness in their own way, in their families and local communities. But since those elected representatives are born with the same selfish impulses as everyone else—the same all-too-human nature that makes government necessary in the first place—the Framers took care to limit their powers and to hedge them with checks and balances, to prevent the servants of the sovereign people from becoming their masters.

The Framers strove to avoid at all costs what they called an Òelective despotism,Ó understanding that elections alone donÕt ensure liberty.

Did they achieve their goal perfectly, even with the first ten amendments that form the Bill of Rights? No—and they recognized that. It took the Thirteenth, Fourteenth, and Fifteenth Amendments—following a fearsome war—to end the evil of slavery that marred the FramersÕ creation, but that they couldnÕt abolish summarily if they wanted to get the document adopted.

Thereafter, it took the Nineteenth Amendment to give women the vote, a measure that followed inexorably from the principles of the American Revolution.

During the ratification debates, one gloomy critic prophesied that if citizens ratified the Constitution, Òthe forms of republican governmentÓ would soon exist Òin appearance onlyÓ in America, as had occurred in ancient Rome.

American republicanism would indeed eventually decline, but the decline took a century to begin and unfolded with much less malice than it did at the end of the Roman Republic.

(EditorÕs note: We strongly disagree with any comparison between America of today and the Roman Republic and Roman Empire.  It is simply wrong!

America has not turned into a vicious, brutal empire, as did Rome.  Quite the opposite, in fact, has occurred.  America, while not as free as it once was, is still a beacon of liberty for the world.)

Nor was it due to some defect in the Constitution, but rather to repeated undermining by the Supreme Court, the president, and the Congress.

The result today is a crisis of legitimacy, fueling the anger with which Americans now glare at one another. Half of us believe we live under the old Constitution, with its guarantee of liberty and its expectation of self-reliance.

The other half believe in a Òliving constitutionÓ—a regime that empowers the Supreme Court to sit as a permanent constitutional convention, issuing decrees that keep our government evolving with modernityÕs changing conditions. The living constitution also permits countless supposedly expert administrative agencies, like the SEC and the EPA, to make rules like a legislature, administer them like an executive, and adjudicate and punish infractions of them like a judiciary.

(EditorÕs note.  The above is not a description of a Òliving constitutionÓ.  It is no constitution!  The US Constitution is very much alive because it can be amended.  However, this requires a lot of support from the American people, who mainly like it the way it is.  So the idea of a Òliving constitutionÓ is a lie.  Those who use those words want to destroy the Constitution, and nothing else.)

To the (Old) Constitutionalists, this government of decrees issued by bureaucrats and judges is not democratic self-government but rather tyranny—hard or soft, depending on whether or not you are caught in the unelected rulersÕ clutches.

To the (phony) Living Constitutionalists, on the other hand, government by agency experts and Ivy League-trained judges—making rules for a progressive society (to use their language) and guided by enlightened principles of social justice that favor the ÒdisadvantagedÓ and other victim groups—constitutes real democracy.  So today we have the ÒFreedom PartyÓ versus the ÒPhony Living Constitution PartyÓ, with unelected bureaucrats and judges saying what fairness is.

Challenging past court decisions.  This is the constitutional deformation that Justice Thomas, an Old Constitutionalist in capital letters, has striven to repair. If the Framers had wanted a constitution that evolved by judicial ruling, Thomas says, they could have stuck with the unwritten British constitution that governed the American colonists in just that way for 150 years before the Revolution.

But Americans chose a written constitution, whose meaning, as the Framers and the state ratifying conventions understood it, does not change—and whose purpose remains, as the Preamble states, to Òsecure the Blessings of Liberty to ourselves and our Posterity.Ó

In ThomasÕs view, there is no nobler or more just purpose for any government. If the Framers failed to realize that ideal fully because of slavery, the Civil War amendments proved that their design was, in ThomasÕs word, Òperfectible.Ó Similarly, if later developments fell away from that ideal, it is still perfectible, and Thomas takes it as his job—his calling, he says—to perfect it. And that can mean that where earlier Supreme Court decisions have deviated from what the document and its amendments say, it is the duty of todayÕs justices to overrule them.

Consequently, while the hallowed doctrine of stare decisis—the rule that judges are bound to respect precedent—certainly applies to the lower courts, Supreme Court justices owe fidelity to the Constitution alone, and if their predecessors have construed it erroneously, todayÕs justices must say so and overturn their decisions.

To contemporary lawyers and law professors, this idea of annulling so-called settled law is shockingly radical. It explains why most of ThomasÕs opinions are either dissents from the CourtÕs ruling or concurrences in the CourtÕs ruling but not its reasoning, often because Thomas rejects the precedent on which the majority relies.

Content with frequently being a minority of one, he points to Justice John Marshall HarlanÕs lone dissent in the 1896 Plessy v. Ferguson case as his model. The majority held in Plessy that separate but equal facilities for blacks in public accommodation were constitutional.

Harlan countered: ÒOur Constitution is color-blind and neither knows nor tolerates classes among citizens. . . . The law regards man as man.Ó ÒDo we quote from the majority or the dissent?Ó Thomas asks. Like Harlan, he is drawing a map for future justices, and he will let history judge his achievement.

***

ThomasÕs opinion in the 2010 McDonald v. Chicago case takes us back to the first of three acts in the drama of constitutional subversion. In that opinion, Thomas agrees with the majority that ChicagoÕs ban on owning handguns violates the Fourteenth Amendment, but disagrees on why.

The Fourteenth Amendment deems everybody born or naturalized in this country, and subject to its jurisdiction, to be a citizen of the United States and of the state where he lives, and declares that no state may Òabridge the privileges or immunities of citizens of the United States.Ó

What the drafters meant by that language was that former slaves were full American citizens, and that no state could interfere with their federally-protected rights—including, said one senator in framing the amendment, Òthe personal rights guaranteed and secured by the first eight amendments of the Constitution.Ó

The rights guaranteed by the Bill of Rights, observed a typical commentator of the time, Òwhich had been construed to apply only to the national government, are thus imposed upon the States.Ó And the feds, the amendmentÕs chief draftsman declared, have the power to enforce them.

Perfectly clear, right? Well, no—not once the Supreme Court got hold of it. As Thomas recounts in McDonald, the CourtÕs first pronouncement on the Fourteenth Amendment came in its 1873 Slaughter-House Cases ruling, which drew a distinction between the privileges and immunities conferred by state citizenship and those conferred by national citizenship. The latter, the Court held, include only such things as the right to travel on interstate waterways and not to be subject to bills of attainder.

All the rights having to do with life, liberty, and property attach only to state citizenship, not national, so they arenÕt protected by the Fourteenth Amendment. One of the four dissenting justices correctly noted that the majority opinion Òturns . . . what was meant for bread into a stone.Ó

The day before the Court handed down its bizarre Slaughter-House decision, the worst atrocity of the terrorist campaign in the South to nullify Reconstruction had occurred.  Black Louisianans, aiming to safeguard Republican victories in contentious recent elections, occupied the courthouse in the county-seat hamlet of Colfax.

Mounted White Liners—an anti-black militia like the KKK—massed in the surrounding woods, prompting more frightened blacks to crowd into the courthouse.  On Easter Sunday, the White Liners set the courthouse ablaze and shot those who ran out the door or jumped out of the windows.  That evening, they shot the captive survivors.

No Louisiana district attorney was going to charge the murderers, so a federal prosecutor convicted three of them of violating a congressional enforcement act that made it a crime to conspire to deprive someone of the privileges or immunities of U.S. citizenship. But in its 1876 Cruikshank decision, the Supreme Court overturned the convictions.

The rights enumerated in the Bill of Rights arenÕt the privileges or immunities conferred by U.S. citizenship, the Court held, citing Slaughter-House as precedent. They come from the Creator, and the first eight amendments merely forbid Congress from abridging them.

Moreover, the murderers were individuals, and the Fourteenth Amendment refers only to states. That was the end of the Fourteenth AmendmentÕs Privileges or Immunities Clause.

In time, the Court rigged a workaround. The Fourteenth Amendment forbids states from taking away a citizenÕs life, liberty, or property without Òdue process of lawÓ—which really means, the Supreme Court asserted out of the blue during the New Deal, that some liberties are so basic that no state can invade them, a doctrine dubbed Òsubstantive due process.Ó

Thomas calls this smoke and mirrors in his McDonald opinion. Even worse, the Òsubstantive due processÓ doctrine allows judges to conjure up imaginary rights out of thin air, making law instead of interpreting the Constitution.

Why, Thomas asks, is the Court treating Slaughter-House and Cruikshank as sacrosanct? It doesnÕt hesitate to overturn laws passed by Congress and signed by the president when it thinks the Constitution doesnÕt allow them. Why should it treat the errors of previous Courts with any more respect?

Yes, the Chicago handgun ban is unconstitutional, Thomas writes. But thatÕs because it abridges citizensÕ Second Amendment right to keep and bear arms as guaranteed by the Privileges or Immunities Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. Why not junk the mumbo-jumbo of Òsubstantive due process,Ó on which the majority of his colleagues are relying in this case, and return to the original text?

 

The commerce clause.  Act Two of the great constitutional subversion stars Franklin Roosevelt, who wrongly diagnosed the cause of the Great Depression as a crisis of overproduction and thus wanted to seize control of the whole U.S. economy to regulate output.  For years, the Court resisted this power-grab, but it buckled under RooseveltÕs threat to enlarge its membership and pack it with judges who would go along.

The ÒCourtÕs dramatic departure in the 1930s from a century and a half of precedent,Ó Thomas says, was a fatal Òwrong turnÓ that marks the start of illegitimate judicial constitution-making.

In his 2005 dissent in Gonzales v. Raich, Thomas cites the New Deal CourtÕs zaniest decision: Wickard v. Filburn, a 1942 ruling in which the Court abjectly capitulated to the federal governmentÕs takeover of the economy under the pretext of the ConstitutionÕs commerce power.

Wickard held that CongressÕs authority to regulate interstate commerce could even forbid a farmer from growing grain only to feed to his own livestock.

In his Gonzales dissent, Thomas hints that the Court should overturn the whole tangle of Commerce Clause cases related to Wickard.

The majority ruling in Gonzales held that federal agents had the authority, under the interstate commerce power—and despite CaliforniaÕs legalization of medical marijuana—to punish two ill Californians who grew and used pot to control their pain. Interstate commerce?

Hardly, Thomas demurs. Like farmer FilburnÕs grain, the pot was never bought or sold, never crossed state lines, and did not affect any national market. ÒNot only does this case not concern commerce,Ó Thomas writes, Òit doesnÕt even concern economic activity.Ó Next thing you know, the feds will be raiding potluck suppers.

 

The regulatory state.  Thomas understands that the New Deal gave rise to an even more powerful device for constitutional demolition than the engorged commerce power—a whole set of administrative agencies like the NLRB and the SEC.

The Supreme Court, Thomas grumbled in the first of a series of 2015 administrative state opinions, has Òoverseen and sanctioned the growth of an administrative system that concentrates the power to make laws and the power to enforce them in the hands of a vast and unaccountable administrative apparatus that finds no comfortable home in our constitutional structure.Ó

For starters, the Constitution vests all legislative powers in Congress, which means that they cannot be delegated elsewhere. As the FramersÕ tutelary philosopher John Locke wrote, the legislature can make laws but it cannot make legislators—which is what Congress does when it invests bureaucrats with the power to make rules that bind citizens.

Nor can the courts delegate judicial power to bureaucrats, as the Supreme Court began doing in a World War II case when it ruled that courts must defer to agenciesÕ interpretations of their own regulations. The CourtÕs rationale was that agencies have technical expertise that judges lack.

ThatÕs not the relevant issue, Thomas contends: ÒThe proper question faced by courts in interpreting a regulation is not what the best policy choice might be, but what the regulation means.Ó And who better to interpret the meaning of words, Thomas asks in Perez v. Mortgage Bankers Association, than a judge?

Worsening this problem, Thomas argues in Michigan v. EPA, is the deference doctrine that the Court hatched in Chevron v. Natural Resources Defense Council in 1984.

This doctrine requires courts to assume that Congress intended that any ambiguity it left in a statute under which an agency operates should be resolved by the agency, not by the courts.

Consequently, Thomas exasperatedly observes, not only do we have bureaucrats making rules like a legislature and interpreting them like a judge, but also the interpretations amount to a further lawmaking power, with no checks or balances whatever.

A not untypical result of all this administrative might, to cite an example recently in the news, was an EPA ruling that a Montana rancher polluted the navigable waterways of the United States by digging two ponds to be filled by a tiny trickle on his land, 40 miles from anything resembling a navigable waterway.

For providing reservoirs to fight potential forest fires, the rancher was fined $130,000 and sentenced to 18 months in prison. (The rancher served his time in prison but continued his legal fight until he died at age 80. A month after his death, the Supreme Court vacated the ruling against him. The Trump administration recently revoked the regulation under which he was convicted.)

 

Making up law rather than judging the constitutionality of laws.  In a virtuoso dissent last year in Carpenter v. U.S., Thomas takes on the third and last act of the CourtÕs attack on the FramersÕ Constitution—the license with which the Court presumes to make up law out of whole cloth, with no prompting from either Congress or the president.

The best recognized example of this is the 1973 Roe v. Wade abortion decision.  Carpenter is less incendiary, but it is deliciously instructive.  A career armed robber, Carpenter claimed that police use of cell phone location data in convicting him violated his Fourth Amendment protection against unreasonable search and seizure.

The Framers, of course, had no cell phones.  But, Thomas notes, Chief Justice William Howard Taft had shown as early as 1928 how to adapt to new circumstances, in a case concerning a telephone wiretap.  The phone lines were outside the convicted bootleggersÕ premises, and conversations arenÕt papers, so federal agents had not invaded their Fourth Amendment-protected Òpersons, houses, papers, [or] effects.Ó Thus, Taft held, no Fourth Amendment-banned search had occurred.

But in a 1967 wiretapping case, the Supreme Court decreed that what the Fourth Amendment really protects is a personÕs Òreasonable expectation of privacy.Ó With this Òreasonable expectation,Ó on which the Carpenter majority rests, Thomas has a field day.

Dictionaries from 1770 to 1828 define a ÒsearchÓ as a looking into suspected places, he notes; transferring Fourth Amendment protection from places to people reads that word out of the text. And Òtheir . . . papers,Ó he points out, canÕt mean someone elseÕs records, so what does the Fourth Amendment have to do with a subpoena for the phone companyÕs files?

And finally, Thomas asks, whoÕs to decide what a ÒreasonableÓ expectation is?  That is a policy determination, not a judicial one—so shouldnÕt Congress decide?

Nevertheless, Chief Justice Roberts cast the deciding vote to uphold this nonsense, in line with half a century of Court-created rights that subverted the authority of the police to fight crime and of teachers and principals to discipline disruptive students.

***

About Justice Thomas.  In conclusion, let me shift my focus from constitutional law to ethics.  It takes a certain kind of character to be capable of liberty, and Clarence Thomas embodies that character. Indeed, his character is bound up with his jurisprudence in an exemplary way.

Born in a shanty in a swampy Georgia hamlet founded by freed slaves, Thomas enjoyed a few Huck Finn-like years, until his divorced mother moved him and his younger brother to a Savannah slum tenement. On her meager maidÕs wages, her children knew Òhunger without the prospect of eating and cold without the prospect of warmth,Ó the Justice recalls.

After a year of this, ThomasÕs mother sent her two little boys a few blocks away, to live with her father and step-mother, a magical, Oliver Twist-like transformation.

ThomasÕs grandfather, Myers Anderson, the self-made if semi-literate proprietor of a modest fuel oil business, lived in a sparkling clean cinderblock house with porcelain plumbing, a full fridge, and a no-excuses childrearing code that bred self-discipline and self-reliance.

A convert to Catholicism, Anderson sent his grandsons to a strict parochial school—segregated like everything else in mid-century Savannah, but teaching that all men are created equal—and he put them to work delivering oil after school and on weekends.

Summer vacation was no holiday for the boys: with their grandfather, they built a house on 60 rural acres. Thereafter they tilled the fields every summer, harvested the crops, and butchered livestock for winter food.

Anderson urged them on with his rich stock of moral maxims, including, ÒWhere thereÕs a will, thereÕs a way.Ó  There wasnÕt a spare minute in the year for the boys to fall into street culture, which Anderson feared.

These lessons in self-reliance formed the bedrock of ThomasÕs worldview. He temporarily flouted them, he recounts, during his student black-radical phase, when he and his college comrades spouted off about how they were Òoppressed and victimizedÓ by Òa culture irretrievably tainted by racism.Ó

Visits home became Òquite strained,Ó he recalls. ÒMy grandfather was no victim, and he didnÕt send me to school to become one.Ó

By ThomasÕs senior year, he had snapped out of it. His old self-reliance expanded from a personal creed to a political one, as he reflected upon how much his college stance of victimhood had threatened to diminish and impede him, especially compared to his grandfatherÕs heroic independence.

He also pondered deeply the harms that affirmative action—purportedly AmericaÕs atonement for its historic sins—had done to his black classmates at Holy Cross and Yale Law School.

Thomas saw that it led to failure and grievance by placing smart but ill-prepared kids in out-of-their-league institutions and branding successes like him with the imputation of inferiority.  His nine years as an influential federal civil rights leader, running the civil rights division of President ReaganÕs Department of Education and then the Equal Employment Opportunity Commission, confirmed his impression that Òthere is no governmental solutionÓ to black AmericaÕs problems—a conclusion underlying the anti-affirmative action opinions he has written on the Court.

In this equal opportunity nation, black citizens must forge their own fate, like all other Americans.  Where thereÕs a will, thereÕs a way.

Regardless of race, everybody faces adversity and must choose whether to buckle down and surmount it, shaping his own fate, or to blame the outcome on powerful forces that make him ineluctably a victim—forces that only a mighty government can master.

The FramersÕ Constitution presupposes citizens of the first kind.  Without them, and a culture that nurtures them, no free nation can long endure.

 

 

Home | Hair Analysis | Saunas | Books | Articles | Detox Protocols

Courses | About Dr. Wilson | The Free Basic Program